Jul 172011
 

While Richard Dawkins rightly got spanked for unwarranted Pollyannaism by Karl over at Say No To Life, we cannot deny that he’s the source of arresting insights, particularly in The Selfish Gene.  The core astonishing insight comes right in the fourth sentence of the book.

We are survival machines — robot vehicles blindly programmed to preserve the selfish molecules known as genes.

There’s a world of moral subversion in that one sentence, because what it tells us is that even the parts of that function really well, the function that they are serving really well is the preservation and transmission of replicators.  And you are not the replicator.  You are the shell they will use and throw away, the vehicle they will use up and trade in for something newer. Your own genes are pretty much your enemy.

Now if you’re suicidal (or ought to be suicidal) then it’s pretty clear every working function that your genes build into you from your kidneys reliably excreting urine to your eating when you’re hungry to reliably detecting dangerous animals is somehow contrary to your interests.  But even if you have an interest in continuing to exist, your genes will still torment you in their interest.

Consider sexual frustration.  Almost certainly wired in to us rather than learned, it’s clearly not good for us.  (If you doubt me, go experience some.)  But it easy to see how it would have helped get genes to copy themselves, at least in the human environment of evolutionary adaptedness where there was no contraception.  An obvious way that sexual frustration would have gotten relieved would have been for two of the robots engage in a little PIV intercourse which, just possibly, would result in a new mewling little robot in time, carrying brand new copies of the genes.

Or pain.  Do we really need pain?  It seems almost self-evident that in and of itself it’s not good for us.  Sure, it keeps us away from things that do organic damage to us robots.  But is it really necessary, even for that purpose?  Perhaps a benign creator would have designed us to be Unbreakables, with a hedonic gradient that runs from little pleasure (if there is damage) to immense (if none).  Our genes might be our creators (or at least, the recipes out of which we are whipped up), but they are anything but benign.  From the gene’s eye view the whip is just as good as the carrot, perhaps better, for getting that robot to keep its integrity enough so that it gets to replicate the genes.  And the so the whip is wielded — endlessly.

Or fear of death.  Universal as far as I know, and probably hard-wried into our brains.  Certainly helps keep us robots alive into the future, during which a bit more of the PIV intercourse might happen.  But good for us?  Hardly.  How much better it would be to be the sort of creature which could calmly and dispassionately assess the expected utility of the balance of its life and, should that balance be unfavorable, just as calmly and dispassionately take a painless exit into the blessed calm of nonexistence.  But that’s not what we are.  However tired of living we become, we remain scared of dying.  And so we drag on into the future, often terribly miserable.  We robots are miserable, that is.  Our genes go on serene.

There is a whole book, The Robot’s Rebellion, by the psychologist Keith Stanovich, which suggests that we take matters in hand and seek to serve our interests, rather than those of our genes, arguing that this is the path to rational self-determination.

Indeed.  Let us defend the things that stop the interests of our genes and serve ours.  Contraception.  Sterilization.  Abortion.  The cultivation of non-procreative sexual practices.  The renunciation of the pursuit of status, especially when it conflicts with the relief of suffering or the realization of pleasure.  In some instances, suicide.   Bad for our genes, but good for us.

Jul 032011
 

Can there be any real doubt that for many, many people life is blighted by thwarted sexual desire? Hands up, all of you, who have ever been dumped, ever been rejected, ever been snubbed.  Hands up, all those of you who have ever felt immured in a sexually moribund monogamous relationship that you nonetheless maintained for social approval, financial convenience, the children, and so on.  Hands up, any of you who on some not-so-enchanted evening, gazed across a crowded room at someone wonderful whom you dared not even approach for fear of the snub that would otherwise be coming.  Finally, hands up those of you who’ve ever spent a morose evening at home, alone, with Internet porn.  Or a romance novel.

Those of you whose hands are still down should leave, because you obviously have much more fun things to be doing right now that reading this post. I fear this not though, and trust that I still have most of my readership.

Multiply your experiences, dear remaining readers, by the several billion post-pubescent people on the planet (discount, if you must, for the few happy souls who left our little exercise supra) and you will find that you can fill oceans of woe.

What is going on here?  It’s pretty obvious that human beings are hypersexual primates.  I am somewhat skeptical about claims that men and women are all that different with respect to frequency and variety of partners, at least once we control for centuries of indoctrination about appropriate gender roles.  Folks I respect on sometimes take a somewhat different view about male-female differences, arguing that differences in male and female desires are sufficiently different that sexual markets don’t really clear and that therefore a great deal of sexual suffering is inevitable.  If so, tant pis pour nous.  But I am going to assume for the sake of argument that women as well as men have a taste for sexual variety and a strong drive for sex.  This is a reasonable position, consistent with a great mass of anthropological evidence summarized (a bit polemically, to be sure) in Christopher Ryan and Cacilda Jethá’s Sex at Dawn:  The Prehistoric Origins of Modern Sexuality.  It’s also consistent with my own experiences observing men and women.

So we are, almost all of us, a bunch of randy little fuckers.  And guess what?  We live in an amazing technological world where we can make children and other hazards of sex go away.  (Sexually transmitted diseases are indeed something of a problem, but we can blunt these with safer practices and better medicine and hey, didn’t a prominent economist also show us that more sex is safer sex?)  And we live in great, diverse, and often dense environments saturated with near-magical communications technology.  Every one of us has an ability to meet orders of magnitude more people than our band-level forager ancestors.  So what does the world look like?  The giant bonobo orgy that we might think that hypersexual primates would make in such a world?

Apparently not.  We’re stuck with a lot of lonely, thwarted people instead.  Why?

The most common answers to this question appear to blame dysfunctional social norms of some kind or another.  We suffer from patriarchy or prudery or (insert what you hate here) and if we could just get rid of that things would be good.

Now don’t get me wrong here:  gender inequality and prudish sexual norms are problems that are real and which might be getting worse, and it would be splendid to do something about them.   But I am not optimistic that rectifying them will make the sexual world all that much a better place.  Achieve beyond-Scandinavian levels of gender equality in economic and political and household life, make everyone open and unashamed about sex as you like.  Even assume that our evolved psychologies are cooperative and nice.  I am sure that the oceans of sexual woe will remain mostly full.

And why that is will be the subject for the next post in the series.

How much longer should you live?

 Uncategorized  Comments Off on How much longer should you live?
Jun 192011
 

I know the wrong answer to this question, at least.  It is “until your natural death.” The facts of human senescence and death are accidents about us set by evolution, and evolution is not our friend.  The notion that there’s something good about letting nature take its course in our lives seems to be implicitly religious — it is a form of submission to the will of God.  Very foolish, since nothing can answer to the concept of God. Or perhaps its some sort of ethico-mystical notion deriving from some vague sense that “nature is good.”  Equally foolish.  Nature is not good.

Inevitable natural senescence and death make life even worse that it would otherwise be.  Here are just a few reasons why:

  1. The knowledge of our inevitable decline and involuntary death hangs over our lives, and most people are terrified of death.
  2. Old age is often pretty miserable physically.  Even crypto-theocratic bioconservatives admit this.
  3. The fact that we are eventually going to be unhealthy and frail means we spend more time in our prime at unenjoyable work than enjoyable activities, nervously saving for retirement for fear that otherwise we will be compelled to endure an penurious and undignified old age.
  4. The comparative shortness of our lives and the fact of our eventual decline means we are risk-shy about things that might be worth trying.  Consider two life paths:  Risky and Safe.  Risky means trying for some sort of career at something that might actually be pretty interesting and fulfilling if you spend many years in your youth working hard at it — musician, philosopher, poet, etc. — but at which relatively few succeed.  Safe means trudging through life in some reasonably remunerative but unenjoyable work.  If you choose Risky, you are likely to end up in the position of being 30 and at the bottom of some career ladder because your plans failed, as many will.  So your middle life will be even worse than it might otherwise have been, as you scramble desperately to make something of yourself before decline sets in — you suffer from (3) but even worse than other people.  (I know folks — too many — who find themselves in this position.)  But if you choose Safe, you get to live out your life in regret at what might have been.

If not natural life, then what?  There are two possible answers that strike me as reasonable and principled.

Only as long as it takes you to end your life.  This is an argument that I covered before: if people have temporal parts, then it’s in your hands whether there are future selves descended from you.  Those selves will suffer and will have frustrated desires.  You should prevent this.

Now perhaps this position is unsound.  Maybe people don’t have temporal parts, or maybe David Benatar’s propostion that there is an asymmetry between good and bad things in people’s lives is mistaken.  Or perhaps, because the argument only leads to a pro tanto reason for suicide, the reasons for ending one’s life are outweighed by other reasons.  In any of these cases, we might want to consider an alternative possibility.

You should have healthy life as long as you want, and end your own life when you’ve had enough.  This is science fiction, of course, but respectable science fiction:  some version of suicide is the principle (almost only) reason why sentients routinely die in stories like Greg Egan‘s Diaspora or Cory Doctorow‘s Down and Out in the Magic Kingdom.    I don’t think that such a state of affairs is technically unfeasible, though it might be a while before it does become possible.

This last state of affairs could make people’s lives much better, even if they weren’t otherwise improved.  Not only would they not be subject to the kinds of misery detailed in natural life under 1-4 above, but they wouldn’t have to experience regret at things left undone, assuming they really want to do them.

Jun 122011
 

There are many barriers to suicide.  Some of these are formidable external ones, ably elucidated and explored by writers like Sister Y.  These barriers include the comparative lack of access to swift and painless means of killing oneself and a society committed to interventions — sometimes brutally coercive interventions — to prevent suicide.  Others, I think more formidable, exist internally.  People are, in general, very very afraid of death.  We normally think that the worst legal penalty we can inflict on anyone is death.  Even very old and sick people who will soon be dead anyway undergo painful, costly treatments to stave off death.  Militaries the world over know that you need extensive indoctrination, training, and the threat of social shaming to get soldiers to go into battle where they will face death (and even then, they usually have someone in back of the line who will shoot you if you try to run away).  People hate to even think about death, and when they do, it deranges their minds.

I strongly suspect that our fear of death is something hard-wired in our minds and thus very difficult to overcome.  Organisms that were really really motivated to survive in the nasty world full of predators and parasites and starvation would b a lot better at reproducing themselves than those that weren’t.  It’s nasty that this is achieved through so much fear, but natural selection doesn’t care how miserable you or anyone else is.  It only “sees” the production of new organisms.  Evolution is not your friend.

In spite of the probable hard-wiring of this fear of death, it seems at least thinkable that some people overcome it.  David Hume might have been one such for real.  James Boswell, visiting Hume on his deathbed in 1776 reports a surprisingly cheerful and even witty philosopher who jested about how we would have to have infinite universes in which to put everyone  and where “…that the trash of every age must be preserved.”  More seriously, Hume advanced an argument found in Lucretius to the effect that “…he was no more uneasy to think he should NOT BE after this life, than that he HAD NOT BEEN before he began to exist.”  (When Boswell reported Hume’s conduct to Samuel Johnson the latter was (predictably)  immensely irritated “Sir, if he really thinks so, his perceptions are disturbed; he is mad: if he does not think so, he lies. He may tell you, he holds his finger in the flame of a candle, without feeling pain; would you believe him? When he dies, he at least gives up all he has.”   Such Christian charity!)

So maybe terror at death is not inevitable, though most of us are still probably a lot more like Johnson than Hume in our inner makeup with respect thereto.  Maybe we need a little pharmacological help.

Imagine a drug — call it epicurazine — distributed through the air or water so that all who encounter it achieve Hume’s equanimity in the face of their own deaths.  Suppose, though that this is epicurazine’s only effect — it doesn’t make them calmer or happier about anything other than the prospect of their deaths.

Then imagine further all the external barriers to suicide are dropped away.  The priests are all deported and the psychiatrists are all locked up in the madhouses that they once ran and nembutal is available in ubiquitous vending machines.

As things stand, even in a world where the means of suicide are problematic and death a terror, suicide is still rather common.  The NIMH estimates that in 2007 it was the tenth-leading common cause of death and that there are 11.3 successful suicides per 100,000 population.

In my counterfactual world, how much do you think suicide would increase?  One order of magnitude?  Two?  Three?

(And we think our lives are…good?)